9.6 Strict categories
Definition 9.6.1.
A strict category is a precategory whose type of objects is a set.
In accordance with the mathematical red herring principle, a strict category is not necessarily a category. In fact, a category is a strict category precisely when it is gaunt (\autorefct:gaunt). Most of the time, category theory is about categories, not strict ones, but sometimes one wants to consider strict categories. The main advantage of this is that strict categories have a stricter notion of “sameness” than equivalence, namely isomorphism (or equivalently, by \autorefct:cat-eq-iso, equality).
Here is one origin of strict categories.
Example 9.6.2.
Let be a precategory and an object. Then there is a precategory as follows:
-
•
Its objects consist of an object and a monomorphism . (As usual, is a monomorphism (or is monic) if .)
-
•
Its morphisms from to are arbitrary morphisms from to in (not necessarily respecting and ).
An equality of objects in consists of an equality and an equality , which by \autorefct:idtoiso-trans is equivalently an equality . Since hom-sets are sets, the type of such equalities is a mere proposition. But since and are monomorphisms, the type of morphisms such that is also a mere proposition. Thus, if is a category, then is a mere proposition, and hence is a strict category.
This example can be dualized, and generalized in various ways. Here is an interesting application of strict categories.
Example 9.6.3.
Let be a finite Galois extension of fields, and its Galois group. Then there is a strict category whose objects are intermediate fields , and whose morphisms are field homomorphisms which fix pointwise (but need not commute with the inclusions into ). There is another strict category whose objects are subgroups , and whose morphisms are morphisms of -sets . The fundamental theorem of Galois theory says that these two precategories are isomorphic (not merely equivalent).
Title | 9.6 Strict categories |
---|---|
\metatable |