equivalence of Zorn’s lemma and the axiom of choice
Let X be a set partially ordered by < such that each chain has an upper bound. Define p(x)={y∈X∣x<y}∈P(X). Let p(X)={p(x)∣x∈X}. If p(x)=∅ then it follows that x is maximal.
Suppose no p(x)=∅. Then by the axiom of choice (http://planetmath.org/AxiomOfChoice) there is a choice function f on p(X), and since for each p(x) we have f(p(x))∈p(x), it follows that x<f(p(x)). Define fα(p(x)) for all ordinals
α by transfinite induction
:
f0(p(x))=x
fα+1(p(x))=f(p(fα(p(x))))
And for a limit ordinal α, let fα(p(x)) be an upper bound of fi(p(x)) for i<α.
This construction can go on forever, for any ordinal. Then we can easily construct an injective function from Ord to X by g(α)=fα(p(x)) for an arbitrary x∈X. This must be injective, since α<β implies g(α)<g(β). But that requires that X be a proper class, in contradiction
to the fact that it is a set. So there can be no such choice function, and there must be a maximal element
of X.
For the reverse, assume Zorn’s lemma and let C be any set of non-empty sets. Consider the set of functions F={f∣∀a∈dom(f)(a∈C∧f(a)∈a)} partially ordered by inclusion. Then the union of any chain in F is also a member of F (since the union of a chain of functions is always a function). By Zorn’s lemma, F has a maximal element f, and since any function with domain smaller than C can be easily expanded, dom(f)=C, and so f is a choice function for C.
Title | equivalence of Zorn’s lemma and the axiom of choice |
---|---|
Canonical name | EquivalenceOfZornsLemmaAndTheAxiomOfChoice |
Date of creation | 2013-03-22 12:59:04 |
Last modified on | 2013-03-22 12:59:04 |
Owner | Henry (455) |
Last modified by | Henry (455) |
Numerical id | 10 |
Author | Henry (455) |
Entry type | Proof |
Classification | msc 03E25 |