locale


TopologyMathworldPlanetmath, in its most abstract sense, is the study of a family of subsets, called open sets, of some given set X, when subject to certain conditions based purely on set-theoretic operationsMathworldPlanetmath. Namely, these conditions are that the intersectionMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath of two open sets is an open set, union of open sets is an open set, and that the empty setMathworldPlanetmath and X are themselves open sets. One can thus think of a topology as a certain kind of a latticeMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath L(X) of subsets associated with the set X, and the study of a general topological space can be distilled further, to the study of this particular lattice L(X). In this setting, the basic elements under scrutiny are no longer “points” in X, but elements of L(X). This shift in focus is the starting point of the so-called “pointless topology”, where the study of topology takes on a lattice-theoretic flavor.

Specifically, the lattice L(X) is an example of what is known as a locale. Formally, a locale is a complete latticeMathworldPlanetmath L that is meet infinitely distributive:

x(Y)=(xY)

for any YL, where xY:={xyyY}.

A “pointless” proof. To see that the lattice L(X) of open sets of a topological space X is a locale, we first observe that L(X) is a complete lattice, since arbitrary joins of open sets are open by definition, which is enough to ensure that arbitrary meets exist too (although they are not arbitrary intersections, they are interiors of the intersections). This means that Y and (xY) are both open sets, and hence the expressions in the equality are at least meaningful at this point. Further, (xY)=(xY)x(Y)=x(Y), because xyx(Y) for individual yY. So we are left with showing that x(Y)(xY). Again, this is true at an individual level:

xy(xY). (1)

Let’s write z=(xY). Then the expression above becomes yxz, where x,y,z are all open sets. Put it another way,

y = (yx)(y-x) (2)
z(y-x) (3)
= z(yxc) (4)
= (zy)(zxc) (5)
(zy)(zxc), (6)

where - denotes the set differenceMathworldPlanetmath operator, c is the set complementation, and the interior operator. (6) comes from the fact that y is open. Now, take the union of all yY, and write this union t:=Y={yyY}. Then

t (zt)(zxc) (7)
(zt)(zxc) (8)
= z(txc). (9)

Taking the intersection with x on both sides, we have

tx (z(txc))x (10)
= (zx)((t-x)x) (11)
= (zx) (12)
= zx (13)
z. (14)

Substituting t and z back to their original form, we have x(Y)(xY), which is what we wanted to prove.

Notice that in the proof above, no points of X are employed, and everything is done via basic set operations, as well as extra set operations, such as the interior operator.

Remarks.

  • Another thing worthy of note is the following fact:

    A lattice is a locale iff it is a completePlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath Brouwerian lattice (equivalently a complete Heyting algebra).

    A sketch of proof goes as follows: if L is a locale, then for any a,bL, the element {cacb} is the relative pseudocomplement of a in b. Conversely, if L is a Heyting algebra, then we can use the trick that for every yY, yx(xY), to show x(Y)(xY).

  • Other examples of locales found in topology is the lattice of regular open sets in a topological space X.

  • Complete Boolean algebras also provide examples of locales. But a locale need not be complete Boolean. The interval topology on the real line is such an example.

  • A locale homomorphism ϕ is a lattice homomorphismMathworldPlanetmath between two locales such that arbitrary sups are preserved: ϕ(iI{ai})=iI{ϕ(ai)}.

  • A locale is also called a frame, and a frame homomorphism a locale homomorphism. However, P. T. Johnstone distinguishes the two names when they are considered as categoriesMathworldPlanetmath. The category Fra of frames consists of locales (or frames) as objects, and locale homomorphisms as morphismsMathworldPlanetmath. On the other hand, the category Loc of locales is defined as the opposite category of Fra.

  • In [5], a frame and a locale are two distinct objects. A frame is defined as above. But a locale L is a triple (F,P,), where F is a frame, P is the set of frame homomorphisms from F to {0,1}, the trivial frame (= the trivial Boolean algebraMathworldPlanetmath), and is a subset (relationMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath) of P×F given by fa iff f(a)=1. For each aF, let U(a)={fPfa}. It is not hard to see that the collectionMathworldPlanetmath of all sets of the form U(a) forms a topology on P. As a result, every frame can be viewed as a topology on some set!

References

  • 1 F. Borceux, Handbook of Categorical Algebra 3: Categories of Sheaves, Cambridge University Press (1994).
  • 2 G. Gierz, K. H. Hofmann, K. Keimel, J. D. Lawson, M. W. Mislove, D. S. Scott, ContinuousPlanetmathPlanetmath Lattices and Domains, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2003).
  • 3 P. T. Johnstone, The Art of Pointless Thinking: A Student’s Guide to the Category of Locales, Category TheoryMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath at Work (Bremen, 1990), pp 85-107, Res. Exp. Math., 18, Heldermann, Berlin (1991).
  • 4 P. T. Johnstone, Stone Spaces, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1982).
  • 5 S. Vickers, Topology via Logic, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1989).
Title locale
Canonical name Locale
Date of creation 2013-03-22 16:38:11
Last modified on 2013-03-22 16:38:11
Owner CWoo (3771)
Last modified by CWoo (3771)
Numerical id 12
Author CWoo (3771)
Entry type Definition
Classification msc 06D22
Synonym frame
Synonym frame homomorphism
Related topic CompleteHeytingAlgebra
Defines locale homomorphism