proof of pseudoparadox in measure theory
Since this paradox depends crucially on the axiom of choice
, we will
place the application of this controversial axiom at the head of the
proof rather than bury it deep within the bowels of the argument.
One can define an equivalence relation ∼ on ℝ by the
condition that x∼y if and only if x-y is rational. By
the Archimedean property of the real line, for every x∈ℝ there will exist a number y∈[0,1) such that y∼x.
Therefore, by the axiom of choice, there will exist a choice
function f:ℝ→[0,1) such that f(x)=f(y) if
and only if x∼y.
We shall use our choice function f to exhibit a bijection between [0,1) and [0,2). Let w be the “wrap-around function” which is defined as w(x)=x when x≥0 and w(x)=x+2 when x<0. Define g:[0,1)→ℝ by
g(x)=w(2x-f(x)) |
From the definition, it is clear that, since x∼f(x) and w(x)∼x, g(x)∼x. Also, it is easy to see that g maps [0,1) into [0,2). If f(x)≤2x, then g(x)=2x-f(x)≤2x<2. On the other hand, if f(x)>2x, then g(x)=2x+2-f(x). Since 2x-f(x) is strictly negative, g(x)<2. Since f(x)<1, g(x)>0.
Next, we will show that g is injective. Suppose that g(x)=g(y) and x<y. By what we already observed, x∼y, so y-x is a non-negative rational number
and f(x)=f(y). There are 3
possible cases: 1) f(x)≤2x≤2y In this case, g(x)=g(y)
implies that 2x-f(x)=2y-f(x), which would imply that x=y. 2) 2x<f(x)<2y In this case, g(x)=g(y) implies 2+2x-f(x)=2y-f(x) which, in turn, implies that y=x+1, which
is impossible if both x and y belong to [0,1). 3) 2x<2y<f(x) In this case, g(x)=g(y) implies that 2x+2-f(x)=2y+2-f(x), which would imply that x=y. The only remaining
possibility is that x=y, so g(x)=g(y) implies that x=y.
Next, we show that g is surjective. Pick a number y in [0,2).
We need to find a number x∈[0,1) such that w(2x-f(y))=y.
If f(y)+y<2, we can choose x=(f(y)+y)/2. If 2≤f(y)+y, we can choose x=(f(y)+y)/2-1.
Having shown that g is a bijection between [0,1) and [0,2), we
shall now complete the proof by examining the action of g. As we
already noted, g(x)-x is a rational number. Since the rational
numbers are countable
, we can arrange them in a series r0,r1,r2… such that no number is counted twice. Define Ai⊂C1 as
Ai={x∈[0,1)∣g(x)=ri} |
It is obvious from this definition that the Ai are mutually disjoint. Furthermore, ⋃∞i=1Ai=[0,1) and ⋃∞i=1Bi=[0,2) where Bi is the translate of Ai by ri.
Title | proof of pseudoparadox in measure theory |
---|---|
Canonical name | ProofOfPseudoparadoxInMeasureTheory |
Date of creation | 2013-03-22 14:38:43 |
Last modified on | 2013-03-22 14:38:43 |
Owner | rspuzio (6075) |
Last modified by | rspuzio (6075) |
Numerical id | 10 |
Author | rspuzio (6075) |
Entry type | Proof |
Classification | msc 28E99 |
Related topic | ProofOfVitalisTheorem |