uniqueness of cardinality
Theorem.
The cardinality of a set is unique.
Proof.
We will verify the result for finite sets only.
Suppose A is a finite set with cardinality ∣A∣=n and ∣A∣=m. Then there exist bijections f:ℕn→A and g:ℕm→A. Since g is a bijection, it is invertible
, and g-1:A→ℕm is a bijection. Then the composition
g-1∘f is a bijection from ℕn to ℕm. We will show by induction
on n that m=n. In the case n=1 we have ℕn=ℕ1={1}, and it must be that ℕm={1} as well, whence m=1=n. Now let n≥1∈ℕ, and suppose that, for all m∈ℕ, the existence of a bijection f:ℕn→ℕm implies n=m. Let m∈ℕ and suppose h:ℕn+1→ℕm is a bijection. Let k=h(n+1), and notice that 1≤k≤m. Since h is onto there exists some j∈ℕn+1 such that f(j)=m. There are two cases to consider. If j=n+1, then we may define ϕ:ℕn→ℕm-1 by ϕ(i)=h(i) for all i∈ℕn, which is clearly a bijection, so by the inductive hypothesis n=m-1, and thus n+1=m. Now suppose j≠n+1, and define ϕ:ℕn→ℕm-1 by
ϕ(i)={h(i)if i≠jkif i=j. |
We first show that ϕ is one-to-one. Let i1,i2∈ℕn, where i1≠i2. First consider the case where neither i1 nor i2 is equal to j. Then, since h is one-to-one, we have
ϕ(i1)=h(i1)≠h(i2)=ϕ(i2). |
In the case i1=j, again because h is one-to-one, we have
ϕ(i1)=k=h(n+1)≠h(i2)=ϕ(i2). |
Similarly it can be shown that, if i2=j, ϕ(i1)≠ϕ(i2), so ϕ is one-to-one. We now show that ϕ is onto. Let l∈ℕm-1. If l=k, then we may take i=j to have ϕ(i)=ϕ(j)=k=l. If l≠k, then, because h is onto, there exists some i∈ℕn such that h(i)=l, so g(i)=h(i)=l. Thus g is onto, and our inductive hypothesis again gives n=m-1, hence n+1=m. So by the principle of induction, the result holds for all n. Returning now to our set A and our bijection g-1∘f:ℕn→ℕm, we may conclude that m=n, and consequently that the cardinality of A is unique, as desired. ∎
Corollary.
There does not exist a bijection from a finite set to a proper subset of itself.
Proof.
Without a loss of generality we may assume the proper subset is nonempty, for if the set is empty then the corollary holds vacuously. So let A be as above with cardinality n∈ℕ, B a proper subset of A with cardinality m<n∈ℕ, and suppose f:A→B is a bijection. By hypothesis there exist bijections g:ℕn→A and h:ℕm→B; but then h-1∘(f∘g) is a bijection from ℕn to ℕm, whence by the preceding result n=m, contrary to assumption
.
∎
The corollary is also known more popularly as the pigeonhole principle.
Title | uniqueness of cardinality |
Canonical name | UniquenessOfCardinality |
Date of creation | 2013-03-22 16:26:52 |
Last modified on | 2013-03-22 16:26:52 |
Owner | mathcam (2727) |
Last modified by | mathcam (2727) |
Numerical id | 27 |
Author | mathcam (2727) |
Entry type | Theorem |
Classification | msc 03E10 |
Related topic | cardinality |
Related topic | bijection |
Related topic | function |
Related topic | set |
Related topic | subset |
Related topic | Subset |
Related topic | Bijection |
Related topic | Set |
Related topic | PigeonholePrinciple |