enumerative combinatorics
Enumerative combinatorics deals with the question: if we know that a set S is finite, how can we determine the exact number of elements that S contains?
Basic principles and techniques of enumerative combinatorics include:
-
•
the addition principle;
- •
-
•
the involution principle;
-
•
the inclusion-exclusion principle
; and
-
•
the use of generating functions.
The principles listed above are disarmingly simple and seemingly
obvious. Nonetheless, when used properly they are powerful
tools for producing bijective proofs of combinatorial identities. On
the other hand, while generating functions can frequently be used to
give quick proofs of identities, it is sometimes difficult to extract
combinatorial proofs from such proofs.
The most fundamental principle of enumerative combinatorics and the
basis of all counting is the addition principle. It says that
if S is a finite set, then
|S|=∑x∈S1. |
More generally, if S=A⊔B, then
|S|=∑x∈A⊔B1=∑x∈A1+∑x∈B1=|A|+|B|. |
By induction on n, we also get
|⊔i∈[n]Si|=∑i∈[n]|Si|. |
As an application of the addition principle, we prove the multiplication principle.
Proposition 1.
Multiplication principle. If S and T are finite sets, then
|S×T|=|S|⋅|T|. |
Proof.
By the addition principle,
|S×T|=∑(x,y)∈S×T1. |
But we can write S×T as the disjoint union
S×T=⊔y∈TS×{y}. |
The projection map S×{y}→S is a bijection, so |S×{y}|=|S|. Hence it follows that
|S×T| | =∑y∈T|S×{y}| | ||
=∑y∈T|S| | |||
=|S|⋅∑y∈T1 | |||
=|S|⋅|T|, |
which completes the proof.
∎
The involution principle says that if φ:S→S is an involution, then for any X⊂S, |X|=|φ(X)|. The following example illustrates the involution principle.
Proposition 2.
Enumerating elements of the powerset. Let [n]={1,2,…,n} and let 2[n] be the powerset of [n]. Then the cardinality of 2[n] is 2n.
Proof.
In other words, φ(S) is the symmetric difference of S and
{n} — if n is an element of S, we remove it, and if n is
not an element of S, we insert it. The function φ is an
involution, hence a bijection. Now notice that 2[n-1]⊂2[n] and φ(2[n-1])=2[n]∖2[n-1]. In
other words,
2[n]=2[n-1]⊔φ(2[n-1]). |
Since φ is a bijection, this implies that
|2[n]|=2⋅|2[n-1]|. |
By induction on n we obtain
|2[n]|=2n⋅|2[0]|. |
Now [0]=∅, so 2[0]={∅}. Thus |2[0]|=1, implying that
|2[n]|=2n, |
which is what we wanted to show. ∎
As we have seen above, it is possible to use the addition principle to
count the number of elements in the disjoint union of finite sets.
But what if we want to count the number of elements in a non-disjoint
union of finite sets? The inclusion-exclusion principle gives
us a way to do this. A common way of stating the inclusion-exclusion
principle is as the following proposition.
Proposition 3.
Inclusion-exclusion principle. Let S1,…,Sn be finite sets. Then
|⋃i∈[n]Si|=∑T∈2[n](-1)|T||⋂i∈TSi|. |
The formula in this proposition uses negative numbers. But the core
of the inclusion-exclusion principle is a statement about natural
numbers.
Proposition 4.
Let S and T be finite sets. Then
|S|+|T|=|S∪T|+|S∩T|. |
Thus the lattice of finite subsets of N is a modular lattice
.
Proof.
By the addition principle,
|S|+|T| | =|(S∖T)⊔(S∩T)|+|(T∖S)⊔(S∩T)| | ||
=|S∖T|+|S∩T|+|T∖S|+|S∩T|. |
Now observe that S∪T=(S∖T)⊔(S∩T)⊔(T∖S). So by a second application of the addition principle,
|S∪T|+|S∩T|=|S∖T|+|S∩T|+|T∖S|+|S∩T|. |
Hence |S|+|T|=|S∪T|+|S∩T|. ∎
Title | enumerative combinatorics |
---|---|
Canonical name | EnumerativeCombinatorics |
Date of creation | 2013-03-22 16:45:58 |
Last modified on | 2013-03-22 16:45:58 |
Owner | mps (409) |
Last modified by | mps (409) |
Numerical id | 14 |
Author | mps (409) |
Entry type | Topic |
Classification | msc 05-00 |
Related topic | DijkstrasAlgorithm |
Related topic | RuleOfProduct |