sign relation
A sign relation is a special type of triadic relation that arises in the use of signs to connote meanings and denote objects. If this sounds reminiscent of what we do in applying logic and reasoning to the world, actual and ideal, it is no accident. Indeed, the polymathematician Charles Sanders Peirce famously defined logic as “formal semiotic”, that is, the formal theory of signs.
Contents:
1 History
It is possible to trace the idea of a triadic sign relation back to hints in Plato and what we know of the Stoics, but one of the most detailed early formulations is found in this passage by Aristotle:
Words spoken are symbols or signs of affections or impressions of the soul ; written words are the signs of words spoken. As writing, so also is speech not the same for all races of men. But the mental affections themselves, of which these words are primarily signs , are the same for the whole of mankind, as are also the objects of which those affections are representations or likenesses, images, copies . (Aristotle, De Interpretatione, ).
2 Definition
A definition of sign relations that is explicit enough to support the development of a formal theory was given by C.S. Peirce in the process of defining logic, and so it is informative to view it in that context.
Logic will here be defined as formal semiotic. A definition of a sign will be given which no more refers to human thought than does the definition of a line as the place which a particle occupies, part by part, during a lapse of time. Namely, a sign is something, , which brings something, , its interpretant sign determined or created by it, into the same sort of correspondence with something, , its object, as that in which itself stands to . It is from this definition, together with a definition of “formal”, that I deduce mathematically the principles of logic. I also make a historical review of all the definitions and conceptions of logic, and show, not merely that my definition is no novelty, but that my non-psychological conception of logic has virtually been quite generally held, though not generally recognized. (Peirce, NEM 4, 20–21).
In the general discussion of diverse theories of signs, the question frequently arises whether signhood is an absolute, essential, indelible, or ontological property of a thing, or whether it is a relational, interpretive, and mutable role that a thing can be said to exercise only within a particular context of relationships.
Peirce’s definition of a sign defines it in relation to its object and its interpretant sign, and thus it defines signhood in relative terms, by means of a predicate with three places. In this definition, signhood is a role in a triadic relation, a role that a thing fills in a given context of relationships — it is not an absolute or non-relative property of a thing-in-itself, one that it possesses independently of all relationships to other things.
Some of the terms that Peirce uses in his definition of a sign may need to be elaborated for the contemporary reader.
-
•
Correspondence. The form of correspondence invoked in the above definition is what Peirce elsewhere calls a “triple correspondence”, that is, just another way of referring to the whole triadic sign relation itself. A sign relation, as a triadic relation, may involve various types of binary correspondences or dyadic relations, but it does not reduce to any combination of them. In particular, the triple correspondence that we find in sign relations should not be confused with the sort of “mirror image” correspondence between realities and representations that is debated in contemporary controversies about “correspondence theories of truth”.
-
•
Determination. The concept of determination intended here is much more general than the concept we use in discussing strictly deterministic causal-temporal processes. First of all, we are speaking of a formal or informational determination, as when we say “two points determine a line”. Causal and temporal determinations imply formal and informational determinations, but the converse does not always hold. In addition, we are allowing here for what is called determination in measure, that is, an order of determinism that admits the full spectrum of more determined and less determined relationships.
-
•
Non-psychological. Peirce’s “non-psychological conception of logic” must be distinguished from any variety of anti-psychologism. He was quite interested in matters of psychology and had much to say about them. But logic and psychology operate on different planes of study even when they have occasion to view the same data, as logic is a normative science where psychology is a descriptive science, and so they have very different aims, methods, and rationales.
3 Examples of sign relations
Because the examples to follow have been artificially constructed to be as simple as possible, their detailed elaboration can run the risk of trivializing the whole theory of sign relations. Despite their simplicity, however, these examples have subtleties of their own, and their careful treatment will serve to illustrate many important issues in the general theory of signs.
Imagine a discussion between two people, and , and attend only to that aspect of their interpretive practice that involves the use of the following nouns and pronouns: .
In this setting the object domain is the set of two people, , while the sign system or syntactic domain is the set of four signs, .
In their use of this sign system, and are not only the passive objects of nominative and accusative references but also the active interpreters of the language that they use. The system of interpretation that is associated with each language user can be represented in the form of a triadic relation called the sign relation of that interpreter.
Understood in terms of its set-theoretic extension, a sign relation is a subset of a cartesian product . Here, , , are three sets that are known respectively as the object domain, the sign domain, and the interpretant domain of the sign relation .
Broadly speaking, the three domains of a sign relation can be any sets whatsoever, but the kinds of sign relations that are typically contemplated in computational settings are usually constrained to having . In these situations interpretants are just special cases of signs, and this makes it convenient to lump signs and interpretants together into a single class called the syntactic domain. In the forthcoming examples, and are identical as sets, so the same elements manifest themselves in two different roles of the sign relations in question. When it is necessary to refer to the whole set of objects and signs in the union of the domains , , for a given sign relation , one may refer to this set as the world of and write .
To facilitate an interest in the abstract structures of sign relations, and to keep the notations as brief as possible as the examples become more complicated, it serves to introduce the following general notations:
= Object Domain = Sign Domain = Interpretant Domain
Introducing a few abbreviations for use in considering the present Example, we have the following data:
= = = = = =
In the present Example, = = Syntactic Domain.
The next two Tables give the sign relations associated with the interpreters and , respectively, putting them in the form of relational databases. Thus, the rows of each Table list the ordered triples of the form that make up the corresponding sign relations, . It is often tempting to use the same names for objects and for relations involving these objects, but it is best to avoid this in a first approach, taking up the issues that this practice raises after the less problematic features of these relations have been treated.
= Sign Relation of Interpreter A = Sign Relation of Interpreter B Object Sign Interpretant Object Sign Interpretant “A” “A” “A” “A” “A” “i” “A” “u” “i” “A” “u” “A” “i” “i” “u” “u” “B” “B” “B” “B” “B” “u” “B” “i” “u” “B” “i” “B” “u” “u” “i” “i”
These Tables codify a rudimentary level of interpretive practice for the agents and , and provide a basis for formalizing the initial semantics that is appropriate to their common syntactic domain. Each row of a Table names an object and two co-referent signs, making up an ordered triple of the form that is called an elementary relation, that is, one element of the relation’s set-theoretic extension.
Already in this elementary context, there are several different meanings that might attach to the project of a formal semiotics, or a formal theory of meaning for signs. In the process of discussing these alternatives, it is useful to introduce a few terms that are occasionally used in the philosophy of language to point out the needed distinctions.
4 Dyadic aspects of sign relations
For an arbitrary triadic relation , whether it is a sign relation or not, there are six dyadic relations that are obtained by projecting on one of the planes of the -space . The six dyadic projections of a triadic relation are defined and notated as follows:
= = = = = = = = = = = =
By way of unpacking the set-theoretic notation, here is what the first definition says in ordinary language. The dyadic relation that results from the projection of on the -plane is written briefly as or written more fully as , and it is defined as the set of all ordered pairs in the cartesian product for which there exists an ordered triple in for some interpretant in the interpretant domain .
In the case where is a sign relation, which it becomes by satisfying one of the definitions of a sign relation, some of the dyadic aspects of can be recognized as formalizing aspects of sign meaning that have received their share of attention from students of signs over the centuries, and thus they can be associated with traditional concepts and terminology. Of course, traditions may vary as to the precise formation and usage of such concepts and terms. Other aspects of meaning have not received their fair share of attention, and thus remain anonymous on the contemporary scene of sign studies.
4.1 Denotation
One aspect of a sign’s complete meaning is concerned with the reference that a sign has to its objects, which objects are collectively known as the denotation of the sign. In the pragmatic theory of sign relations, denotative references fall within the projection of the sign relation on the plane that is spanned by its object domain and its sign domain.
The dyadic relation that makes up the denotative, referential, or semantic aspect or component of a sign relation is notated as . Information about the denotative aspect of meaning is obtained from by taking its projection on the object-sign plane, in other words, on the 2-dimensional space that is generated by the object domain and the sign domain . This semantic component of a sign relation is written in any one of the forms, , , , , and it is defined as follows:
Looking to the denotative aspects of and , various rows of the Tables specify, for example, that uses to denote and to denote , whereas uses to denote and to denote . All of these denotative references are summed up in the projections on the -plane, as shown in the following Tables:
Object Sign Object Sign “A” “A” “i” “u” “B” “B” “u” “i”
4.2 Connotation
Another aspect of meaning concerns the connection that a sign has to its interpretants within a given sign relation. As before, this type of connection can be vacuous, singular, or plural in its collection of terminal points, and it can be formalized as the dyadic relation that is obtained as a planar projection of the triadic sign relation in question.
The connection that a sign makes to an interpretant is here referred to as its connotation. In the full theory of sign relations, this aspect of meaning includes the links that a sign has to affects, concepts, ideas, impressions, intentions, and the whole realm of an agent’s mental states and allied activities, broadly encompassing intellectual associations, emotional impressions, motivational impulses, and real conduct. Taken at the full, in the natural setting of semiotic phenomena, this complex system of references is unlikely ever to find itself mapped in much detail, much less completely formalized, but the tangible warp of its accumulated mass is commonly alluded to as the connotative import of language.
Formally speaking, however, the connotative aspect of meaning presents no additional difficulty. For a given sign relation , the dyadic relation that constitutes the connotative aspect or connotative component of is notated as .
The connotative aspect of a sign relation is given by its projection on the plane of signs and interpretants, and is thus defined as follows:
All of these connotative references are summed up in the projections on the -plane, as shown in the following Tables:
Sign Interpretant Sign Interpretant “A” “A” “A” “A” “A” “i” “A” “u” “i” “A” “u” “A” “i” “i” “u” “u” “B” “B” “B” “B” “B” “u” “B” “i” “u” “B” “i” “B” “u” “u” “i” “i”
4.3 Ennotation
The aspect of a sign’s meaning that arises from the dyadic relation of its objects to its interpretants has no standard name. If an interpretant is considered to be a sign in its own right, then its independent reference to an object can be taken as belonging to another moment of denotation, but this neglects the mediational character of the whole transaction in which this occurs. Denotation and connotation have to do with dyadic relations in which the sign plays an active role, but here we have to consider a dyadic relation between objects and interpretants that is mediated by the sign from an off-stage position, as it were. As a relation between objects and interpretants that is mediated by a sign, this aspect of meaning may be referred to as the ennotation of a sign, and the dyadic relation that constitutes the ennotative aspect of a sign relation may be notated as .
The ennotational component of meaning for a sign relation is captured by its projection on the plane of the object and interpretant domains, and it is thus defined as follows:
As it happens, the sign relations and are fully symmetric with respect to exchanging signs and interpretants, so all of the data of is echoed unchanged in and all of the data of is echoed unchanged in .
Object Interpretant Object Interpretant “A” “A” “i” “u” “B” “B” “u” “i”
5 Semiotic equivalence relations
See main entry (http://planetmath.org/SemioticEquivalenceRelation).
Title | sign relation |
Canonical name | SignRelation |
Date of creation | 2013-10-25 23:44:57 |
Last modified on | 2013-10-25 23:44:57 |
Owner | Jon Awbrey (15246) |
Last modified by | Jon Awbrey (15246) |
Numerical id | 33 |
Author | Jon Awbrey (15246) |
Entry type | Definition |
Classification | msc 94A15 |
Classification | msc 94A05 |
Classification | msc 03G15 |
Classification | msc 03E20 |
Classification | msc 03B42 |
Classification | msc 03B10 |
Related topic | RelationTheory |
Related topic | TriadicRelation |
Related topic | SignRelationalComplex |
Related topic | SemioticEquivalenceRelation |
Defines | connotation |
Defines | denotation |
Defines | ennotation |
Defines | interpretant |
Defines | semiotic equivalence |