ordering on cardinalities
When there is a one-to-one function from a set A to a set B, we say that A is embeddable in B, and write A≤B. Thus ≤ is a (class) binary relation on the class V of all sets. This relation is clearly reflexive
and transitive
. If A≤B and B≤A, then, by Schröder-Bernstein theorem
, A is bijective
to B, A∼B. However, clearly A≠B in general. Therefore ≤ fails to be a partial order
. However, since A∼B iff they have the same cardinality, |A|=|B|, and since cardinals are by definition sets, the class of all cardinals becomes a partially ordered set
with partial order ≤. We record this result as a theorem:
Theorem 1.
In ZF, the relation ≤ is a partial order on the cardinals.
With the addition of the axiom of choice
, one can show that ≤ is a linear order on the cardinals. In fact, the statement “≤ is a linear order on the cardinals” is equivalent
to the axiom of choice.
Theorem 2.
In ZF, the following are equivalent:
-
1.
the axiom of choice
-
2.
≤ is a linear order on the cardinals
Proof.
Restating the second statement, we have that for any two sets A,B, there is an injection from one to the other. The plan is to use Zorn’s lemma to prove the second statement, and use the second statement to prove the well-ordering principle (WOP).
- Zorn implies Statement 2:
-
Suppose there are no injections from A to B. We need to find an injection from B to A. We may assume that B≠∅, for otherwise ∅ is an injection from B to A. Let P be the collection
of all partial injective functions from B to A. P, as a collection of relations between B and A, is a set. P≠∅, since any function from a singleton subset of B into A is in P. Order P by set inclusion, so P becomes a poset. Suppose F is a chain of partial functions
in P, let us look at f:=. Suppose . Then and for some . Since is a chain, one is a subset of the other, so say, . Then , and since is a partial function, . This shows that is a partial function. Next, suppose . By the same argument used to show that is a function, we see that , so that is injective. Therefore . Thus, by Zorn’s lemma, has a maximal element
. We want to show that is defined on all of . Now, can not be surjective, or else is a bijection from onto . Then is an injection, contrary to the assumption
. Therefore, we may pick an element . Now, if , we may pick an element . Then the partial function given by
Since is injective by construction, . Since properly extends , we have reached a contradiction
, as is maximal in . Therefore the domain of is all of , and is our desired injective function from to .
- Statement 2 implies WOP:
-
Let be a set and let be its Hartogs number. Since is not embeddable in , by statement 2, is embeddable in . Let be the injection from to is injective. Since is an ordinal
, it is well-ordered. Therefore, as is well-ordered, and because , itself is well-orderable via the well-ordering on .
Since Zorn’s lemma and the well-ordering principles are both equivalent to AC in ZF, the theorem is proved. ∎
Title | ordering on cardinalities |
---|---|
Canonical name | OrderingOnCardinalities |
Date of creation | 2013-03-22 18:50:23 |
Last modified on | 2013-03-22 18:50:23 |
Owner | CWoo (3771) |
Last modified by | CWoo (3771) |
Numerical id | 4 |
Author | CWoo (3771) |
Entry type | Theorem |
Classification | msc 03E10 |
Classification | msc 03E25 |